Unit 1: Logic

1.2 Arguments – Types of Reasoning

The two main types of reasoning involved in the discipline of Logic are deductive reasoning and inductive reasoning.

  • Deductive reasoning is an inferential process that supports a conclusion with certainty.
  • Inductive reasoning is an inferential process providing support strong enough to offer high probability (but not absolute certainty) for the conclusion.

1.2.1 Attributes of Deductive Arguments

Validity

Validity is the attribute of deductive arguments that denotes logical strength. Validity is about the strength of the inference, or reasoning, between the premises and the conclusion. A deductive argument is valid when:

If all its premises were true, then its conclusion must be true, by necessity.

To determine if an argument is valid or invalid (not valid), take these steps:

  1. First assume that the premises are true, even if they are not; just pretend that they are true.
  2. Then ask yourself whether the conclusion would need to be true, assuming/pretending that the premises are true.

Here is an example:

Premise 1: All dogs are snakes.
Premise 2: All snakes are birds.
Conclusion: All dogs are birds.

This is a valid argument because if all of the premises were true then the conclusion would follow by necessity. The argument has logical strength, or validity. Validity is not about the truth of its premises, it is about the form of the argument. In the sample valid argument above, the conclusion is also false, but the argument is valid.

Valid arguments may have:

  • Actually true premises  and actually true conclusion
  • Actually false premises and actually false conclusion (as in the example above)
  • Actually false premises and actually true conclusion

Valid arguments can never have:

  • Actually true premises and actually false conclusion.

In a valid deductive argument, if the premises are true, it is impossible for the conclusion to be false.

It is important to keep in mind that just because an argument does have a possibly valid combination of premise-conclusion truth values (for example, true premises and true conclusion), it is not necessarily valid. A valid argument must also be logically strong. That example with dogs, snakes, and birds is valid, because the reasoning works. If those premises were true, the conclusion would necessarily follow. Even if the premises are true and the conclusion is true, it does not mean that the reasoning is valid.

Here is an example of an argument with true premise and a true conclusion, but the connection (the reasoning) from the premises to the conclusion is not strong and the argument is not valid. The conclusion happens to be true but not due to any reason provided by those premises. The argument’s form is invalid.

Premise 1: All dogs are mammals.
Premise 2: All collies are mammals.
Conclusion: All collies are dogs.

To summarize, a valid deductive argument is one where it would be impossible for the conclusion to be false given that the premises were true. The conclusion follows necessarily from the logical connections or reasoning established by the premises.

Soundness

Soundness is the attribute of a deductive argument that denotes both the truth of its premises and its logical strength. A deductive argument is sound when:

  1. It is valid, and
  2. It has all true premises.

For example:

Premise 1: All cats are mammals.
Premise 2: All mammals are animals.
Conclusion: All cats are animals.

This argument is sound because (1) it is valid (the premises support the conclusion by necessity) and (2) all of the premises are actually true!

On the other hand, the example above used to demonstrate validity (with dogs, snakes and birds) is not sound, because it does not have all (any!) true premises. (But it’s form is still valid.)


1.2.2 Attributes of Inductive Arguments

Inductive Strength

Inductive strength is the attribute of inductive arguments that denotes logical strength. An inductive argument is inductively strong when you have the following:

If all its premises were true, then it its highly likely or probable that its conclusion would also true.

“Strong” and “weak” are the terms used to describe the possibilities for the logical strength of inductive arguments. To determine if an argument is strong or weak, take these steps:

  1. First assume the premises are true, even if they are not; just pretend for now that they are true.
  2. Then ask yourself whether it is likely/probable that the conclusion would be true, assuming/pretending that those premises are true.

Here is an example:

Premise 1: Most peacocks eat oatmeal for breakfast.
Premise 2: This bird is a peacock.
Conclusion: Therefore, this bird probably eats oatmeal for breakfast.

This argument is inductively strong because if all its premises were true, then it would be highly likely or probable that its conclusion would also true.

Inductively strong arguments may have:

  • Actually true premises and actually true conclusion
  • Actually false premises and actually false conclusion
  • Actually false premises and actually true conclusion

Inductively strong arguments cannot have:

  • Actually true premises and actually false conclusion

To summarize, a strong inductive argument is one where it is improbable for the conclusion to be false, given that the premises are true. A weak inductive argument is one where the conclusion probably would not follow from the premises, if they were true.

Cogency

Cogency is the attribute of an inductive arguments that denotes the truth of its premises and its logical strength. An inductive argument is cogent when:

  1. It is inductively strong, and
  2. It has all true premises.

Here’s an example:

Premise 1: Europa (a moon of Jupiter) has an atmosphere containing oxygen.
Premise 2: Oxygen is required for life.
Conclusion: Thus, there could be life on Europa.

This argument is cogent because (1) it is inductively strong (if the premises were true, then the conclusion would probably be true) and (2) the premises actually are true.

On the other hand, the example above concerning peacocks, used to demonstrate inductive strength, is not cogent, because it does not have all true premises.


1.2.3 Good Arguments

The important take-away from the information on the attributes of both deductive and inductive arguments is this:

good argument proves (or establishes) its conclusion, and it has two key features:

  1. It is logically strong.
  2. All of its premises are true.

Logical Strength

Logical strength is the degree of support that the premises, if true, confer on the conclusion. This attribute applies to both deductive arguments (by virtue of validity) and inductive arguments (by virtue of inductive strength.)

  • A good deductive argument is not only valid, but is also sound.
  • A good inductive argument is not only inductively strong, but is also cogent.

Videos

These videos deepen your understanding of the material covered in section 1.2 and to provide insight on material coming up in section 1.3.

Deduction and Induction

Validity, Soundness, Strength and Cogency


Check Your Understanding


Review Summary: Attributes of Arguments

Deductive Arguments

Premises Conclusion Strength? Good Argument?
TRUE TRUE Valid if logically strong Sound if valid
TRUE FALSE Never Valid Never Sound
FALSE TRUE Valid if logically strong Never Sound
FALSE FALSE Valid if logically strong Never Sound
Note that a deductive argument with false premises can be valid, but never sound.

Inductive Arguments

Premises Conclusion Strength? Good Argument?
TRUE TRUE Inductively Strong if logically strong Cogent if inductively strong
TRUE FALSE Never Strong Never Cogent
FALSE TRUE Inductively Strong if logically strong Never Cogent
FALSE FALSE Inductively Strong if logically strong Never Cogent
Note that an inductive argument with false premises can be inductively strong, but never cogent.

Good Arguments

Argument Type Logically Strong Good Arguments
Deductive Valid Sound: Valid and actually true premises
Inductive Strong Cogent: Strong and actually true premises
A GOOD argument is logically strong and has all true premises.

 

License

Icon for the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License

Introduction to Philosophy Copyright © 2024 by Kathy Eldred is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted.